.

Sunday, January 26, 2014

Some Basic Consideration Of Discourse Reference

Some Basic Considerations of Discourse Reference By Wu Hailan 98013 We deal that the counterbalance psychoanalyst necessarily takes a pragmatic border on to the dealledge of language in use. They have to take none of the lingual scope in which a humans of cover call for alongs. Because the analyst is probe the use of language in mount by a talker/writer, he is much relate with the kinship surrounded by the verbaliser system building block unit and the utterance, on the contingent join of use, than with the possible kinship of one destine to anformer(a), regardless of their use. They be always describing what speakers and he arers are doing, and not the relationship which exists mingled with one sentence or proposition and another. In this paper, I give do many basic researches ab disclose one opinion of treatment outline----- discourse link up, and what I mention hither go away prove how substantial it is to have a good command of it. It fi nish support us to remediate the skills of reading and writing a deal. The traditional semantic judgement of citation is one in which the relationship of point of generator is taken to employ between regulateulations in a text and entities in the founding, and that of co-reference between mirror images in different parts of a text. In the traditional approach, the term ¡®reference¡¯ is utilize, to conquerher with ¡® intelligence¡¯, to discuss lexical kernel. The meaning of a lexical power point, such(prenominal) as chicken, is partially fixed by its sense, that is, the component becomingties of ¡® proclaim¡¯, ¡®feathered¡¯, etc., and also inflexible by its reference, that is , the set of objects in the world to which the look bottom be slide d professly applied. Lyons provides a evented number of the background and issues involved in this character and suggests that the term ¡®reference¡¯ is better re transportd by the term ¡® cite¡ ¯ in considerations of lexical meaning. We s! hall follow his practice and read that, in discussions of lexical semantics, it may prove useful to claim that a lexical item has sense and denotation. This distinction is also for the most part cover by the damage ¡®intension¡¯ and ¡®extension¡¯, more ordinarily found, in formal semantics. The term reference can thence be taken out of discussions of lexical meaning and reticent for that portion whereby speakers (writers) indicate, via the use of a linguistic look, the entities they are public lecture ( writing) about. It is often considered important in formal semantics that the expression utilise to refer to an entity must, in its exposition, be true of the entity. However, ¡®correct¡¯ reference in this sense is not normally the measure by which language-users run when they refer to person in discourse. In fact, it involve not even be the case that the speaker believes the description to be true, but quite an that he believes that, by victimisation this expression, he go away enable his meeter to separate out the think denotative. Thus, the innovation which interests the discourse analyst is not that of correct (true) reference, but successful reference. Successful reference depends on the attendee¡¯s identifying, for the purposes of understanding the current linguistic message, the speaker¡¯s intended referent, on the terra firma of the referring expression employ. This plump occlusive introduces the notion of ¡®identifying the speaker¡¯s intended referent¡¯ which is of crucial importance in any consideration of the rendition of referring expressions in discourses. Despite the fact that, in virtually analyses, the apparent horizon is put forward that both(prenominal) linguistic expressions have crotchety and self-directed reference, we shall insist that, whatever the form of the referring expression, its denotative function depends on the speaker¡¯s intention on the special occasion of use. Next , I exit say something about on what the hearer base! s his identification of the speaker¡¯s intended referent, and what forms referring expression take. Firstly, I talk about reference and discourse proto slips. An uninflected distinction can be made between what is in the world and what we might describe as the mold in the mind of a person of what is in the world. This latter concept we can treat as the person¡¯s imitation, or illustration, of the world. More to the point, in paying attention to a backing piece of discourse, as a sample of experience of the world, the individualististic may score a specific office of this detail experience of the world which, of course, will be integrated, to a degree, at heart his more frequent representation of the world. This specific representation, or model, arising from a crabbed discourse, we can characterise as the individual¡¯s discourse representation. Given this extremely simple reading of what a discourse representation might be, we can go on to suggest that whe n a writer (speaker) produces a piece of discourse, it will be ground on his individual representation of a particular declare of affairs. The reader ( hearer), as he receives the discourse, will normally try to build a representation ( his model ) of the state of affairs communicated by the speaker. This basic one-way version of discourse communication is quite obviously an outline which truly takes place between speakers¡¯ versions of hearers¡¯ version of speakers¡¯ version (and so on) of representation, in normal discourse situations. However, this basic version should concede us to see that there is likely to be an built-in couple between what is in the speaker¡¯s representation and what is the hearer¡¯s representation. At best, the hearer is likely to aim at a representation which is only partially corresponding to the speaker¡¯s and which, moreover, can only ever be a partial reflection of the so-called ¡®actual¡¯ state of affairs which existed in the world. A strong version of this view would be that ¡! ®human understand what is said to them in terms of their own familiarity and beliefs about the world. When a speaker, on the substructure of his representation, uses an expression to deplume out an individual entity, he will typically take into consideration those features of his hearer¡¯s create discourse representation which he can depend on the hearer creation able to use in identifying the intended referent. The precondition of a similar general expression of the world, sociocultural conventions, cognisance of context and communicative conventions are some of the pertinent features. The hearer, for his part, will also generally assume that the speaker is operate with those assumptions and will base his identification of the intended referent on an definition of the linguistic expression which is consistent with those features which are the basis of the world created by his developing discourse representation. Generally, then, the hearer will build a representation o f the discourse which will prevail representation of entities introduced by the speaker through the use of referring expressions. Clearly, in evidence for the hearer to do this, he must operate with some regular notion of what types of expressions, under what conditions, are apply to refer to entities. Secondly, I talk about referring expression. thither is a considerable literature in philosophy and linguistics on the temper and status of expressions which can, or cannot, be apply to refer. Since much of the grapple revolves around issues of truth, existence and uniqueness, and concerns itself with single system sentences, cited in isolation from any communicative context, the controversies may appear rather cryptical to the practical discourse analyst. After all, the discourse analyst is more often than not concerned, in his investigation, with data which is the output of the actual use of linguistic expression in a definable context for a particular purpose, rather tha t the potential use of such expression. There are som! e obscure expressions such as a man, a rainbow, a fine-looking girl, a line, which are typically used to introduce entities into the discourse. In each of these examples, we can say that the speaker intends the hearer to take in that there is an individual entity referred to by the expression used. It does not see to be a prerequisite condition of this type of earlier reference that the hearer should be able to ¡®identify unambiguously¡¯, in any exact sense, the individual referred to. There are, of course, identifiable circumstances in which an vague expression is unlikely to be taken as a referring expression. The other generally recognized condition in which doubtful noun phrases may not be treated as referential is when they appear in linguistic contexts which are ¡®referentially opaque¡¯. denotive opacity can occur after certain verbs, such as look for and want. The virtuous examples take the following form: 1)         Marion is looking for a sorry. 2)         Virginia wants a new job. It may be that, in uttering these sentences on a particular occasion, a speaker does have a ¡®specific¡¯ referent in mind. That is , the analysis would be that there is a rubber which Marion is looking for. However, the indefinite expression, a rubber, could be used to mean ¡®any rubber¡¯, and in this ¡®non-specific¡¯ reading, it is not being used referentially. It may be that the so-called ¡®ambiguity¡¯ of sentences like 1) and 2) arises because they are cited without contexts. We would suggest that, in the analysis of naturally occurring discourse, the analyst will have micturate contextual or co-textual cues to communicate his assignment of referential or non-referential use to these indefinite expressions. He may also be able to appeal to phonologic or more general paralinguistic clues in deciding when other indefinite expressions, such as someone, something, are being used to refer to a particular ind ividual or not. That is, in uttering the sentences in! 3) and 4) , the speaker can indicate, internationally, for example, that it is his intention to refer to a specific individual. 3)         Someone ( and I know who ) won¡¯t like this proposal. 4)         Someone ( and I don¡¯t know who ) has stolen my bicycle. The other generally discussed type of referring expression is the definite noun phrase. The trope uses of definite noun phrases are in subsequent reference to an entity or to salient objects in the material context. One widely discussed point made by Donnellan is that some definite noun phrases, even as subjects of their sentences, may be used ¡®non-referentially¡¯. Donnellan¡¯s argument is aimed at the prerequisite, in some philosophic approaches to the analysis of definite descriptions, that the expression used must pick our a single individual in the world in order for the reference to be correct. The other is that hearers pick out speakers¡¯ intended referents, on a fairly loose e xplanation of what ¡®attributes¡¯ are included in the definite descriptions. An important point is that our interpretation of expressions such as the chicken and the newspaper, when used referentially, is based on our pragmatic knowledge of the range of reference of such expressions, which is, on a particular occasion of use, strictly labored and ¡®determined by the disposition of the predication, and by the conversational context¡¯. We could say that these factors in find the hearer¡¯s (reader¡¯s ) representation of discourse entities, not only for definite descriptions and proper names, but, more crucially, when pronominals are encountered in discourse. What I mention in a higher place is my basic considerations of discourse reference. It helps us to use language efficiently and understand the discourse well. More attention need to be paid on it when we do the discourse analysis. If you want to get a full essay, order it on ou r website: Ord! erCustomPaper.com

If you want to get a full essay, visit our page: write my paper

No comments:

Post a Comment